Support the IEET




The IEET is a 501(c)3 non-profit, tax-exempt organization registered in the State of Connecticut in the United States. Please give as you are able, and help support our work for a brighter future.



Search the IEET
Subscribe and Contribute to:


Technoprogressive? BioConservative? Huh?
Quick overview of biopolitical points of view




whats new at ieet

What is Transhumanism? – the 3 Supers

Beyond The People’s Climate March

Multitask Humanoid Control with a Brain-Computer Interface

Cell-mediated Delivery of Nanoformulated Antioxidants for Treatment of Neurodegenerative Disorders

Transhumanism - Considering Ideas From Existentialism and Religion

Why and How Should We Build a Basic Income for Every Citizen?


ieet books

A History of Life-Extensionism in the Twentieth Century
Author
Ilia Stambler


comments

instamatic on 'Is Anarchy (as in Anarchism) the Golden Mean of the future?' (Sep 17, 2014)

instamatic on 'Transhumanism - Considering Ideas From Existentialism and Religion' (Sep 17, 2014)

spud100 on 'Transhumanism - Considering Ideas From Existentialism and Religion' (Sep 16, 2014)

dobermanmac on 'Can Brain Implants Make Us Smarter?' (Sep 15, 2014)

dobermanmac on 'Genetically Engineered Ethical Super Babies?' (Sep 15, 2014)

ANB2015 on 'MMR Vaccines and Autism: Bringing clarity to the CDC Whistleblower Story' (Sep 14, 2014)

PhilOsborn on 'Do Cognitive Enhancing Drugs Actually Work?' (Sep 13, 2014)







Subscribe to IEET News Lists

Daily News Feed

Longevity Dividend List

Catastrophic Risks List

Biopolitics of Popular Culture List

Technoprogressive List

Trans-Spirit List



JET

Transhumanism and Marxism: Philosophical Connections

Sex Work, Technological Unemployment and the Basic Income Guarantee

Technological Unemployment but Still a Lot of Work…

Hottest Articles of the Last Month


Enhancing Virtues: Self-Control and Mindfulness
Aug 19, 2014
(9132) Hits
(0) Comments

“Lucy”: A Movie Review
Aug 18, 2014
(6907) Hits
(0) Comments

Enhancing Virtues: Caring (part 1)
Aug 29, 2014
(5090) Hits
(1) Comments

An open source future for synthetic biology
Sep 9, 2014
(4198) Hits
(0) Comments



IEET > Life > Vision > Affiliate Scholar > John Danaher

Print Email permalink (7) Comments (2454) Hits •  subscribe Share on facebook Stumble This submit to reddit submit to digg


The Lucretian Symmetry Argument (Part One)


John Danaher
By John Danaher
Ethical Technology

Posted: Feb 15, 2013

Death looms large for most of us, even if we try not to think about it. But should we be worried at the prospects of our eventual demise? Should we do everything we can to avoid it (e.g. by opting for cryopreservation)? Or should we approach it with indifference and equanimity?

The Epicurean school of thought supports the latter view — that of equanimity and indifference — with two classic arguments. The first, which we might call the experiential blank argument, holds that death is nothing to us because “we” won’t be around to experience it. This argument was the subject of a previous series of blog posts. The second, which is typically called the Lucretian symmetry argument, is the subject of this series of blog posts.

I’ll spread the discussion of the argument over a couple of blog posts. In the remainder of this post, I’ll outline the general form of the argument and consider possible strategies for responding to it. I’ll also consider Brueckner and Fischer’s (B&F’s), by now famous, objection to the argument. In subsequent posts, I will consider Feldman’s recent riposte to B&F and, in turn, their reply to Feldman.


1. What Lucretius Said
Once we get into the debate between Feldman and B&F, things will start to get pretty complex (and, if I’m honest, slightly arcane). But it’s reassuring to know that the debate between these parties is rooted in a fairly simple argument. The argument comes from a couple of passages from Lucretius’s On the Nature of Things. Here they are:
 

“In days of old, we felt no disquiet...So, when we shall be no more - when the union of body and spirit that engenders us has been disrupted - to us, who shall then be nothing, nothing by any hazard will happen any more at all. 
Look back at the eternity that passed before we were born, and mark how utterly it counts to us as nothing. This is a mirror that Nature holds up to us, in which we may see the time that shall be after we are dead.”


The passages present a simple analogy (although you have to get past the archaic language in this translation to see it clearly). The analogy compares two states: (i) post-mortem non-being, or, more simply, “death”; and (ii) pre-natal non-being, which we’ll label PNNB. The suggestion is that these two states are similar in all crucial respects because they both entail our non-existence. The claim is then made that since PNNB “counts to us as nothing” so too should death count to us as nothing.

The phrase “counts to us as nothing” requires some unpacking. As with the other Epicurean arguments about death, there is a danger that we will conflate two distinct conclusions that the arguments might allow us to reach. The first conclusion has to do with the prudential axiology of death (i.e. whether death is good or bad for you). The second conclusion has to do with the psychological attitude one should have toward death (i.e. whether one should be afraid or not). The two conclusions may be connected, but if they are, this connection will have to be made explicit.

That’s exactly what this formal reconstruction of the argument attempts to do (inspired but modified from Feldman):
 

  • (1) The state of pre-natal non-being is not bad for us. 
  • (2) Post-mortem non-being (death) is the same as pre-natal non-being, in all important respects.
  • (3) Therefore, death is not bad for us. 
  • (4) If something is not bad for us, then it is irrational to fear it. 
  • (5) Therefore, the fear of death is irrational.

 


There are two-steps to the argument. The first taking us to the axiological conclusion; the second to the psychological conclusion. The steps are bridged by way of the principle posited in premise (4). One may doubt whether this principle is true. For instance, it could be that we rationally fear things that are not bad for us (e.g. things that are bad for others). I won’t be considering such concerns here (I will do some other time). Instead, I shall assume that prudential badness and the rationality of fear are intimately linked in the manner suggested by premise (4).



This shifts most of the focus back to the first step of the argument. As we can see, that step is strictly analogical in nature. As a result, that part of the argument is not logically sound: the conclusion does not actually follow from the premises as a matter of deductive certainty. This is because, following Douglas Walton, I view analogical arguments as presumptive arguments. These are arguments that lead to defeasible conclusions that can be set aside under certain conditions. Those conditions relate to: (a) the truth of the claim made about the first relevant case; and (b) the strength of the similarity between the two relevant cases: death and PNNB. If the claim made about PNNB is not true, or if the two cases are not similar “in all important respects”, then the conclusion does not follow.

The first possibility — i.e. that PNNB is, contra Lucretius, actually bad for us — will resurface later in the discussion. In the meantime, the second possibility — that death and PNNB differ in certain crucial respects — will monopolise our attention.


2. The Simple Disanalogy and the Parfittian Bias
An obvious difference between PNNB and death is this: our existence precedes our death, but not our PNNB. That much seems banal, even platitudinous in its obviousness, and by itself it does not seem like it could defeat the Lucretian argument. One imagines Lucretius replying with a confident “So what? That’s not a significant difference.”

But maybe he’s wrong. Maybe this difference is significant. Consider the following thought experiment from Derek Parfit:
 

Amnesia Operation: You are in hospital for a serious, and extremely painful operation. The operation cannot be performed with anaesthetic, and the pain is so severe that doctors have decided to administer powerful memory-erasing drugs to everyone who undergoes it, believing that this is the only way for people to overcome the trauma. The medication is administered before the operation and essentially blocks out your memory for several hours on either side of the operation. You awake in your hospital bed, unable to remember what has happened. You ask the nurse on duty, but she can only tell you that either (a) you just woke up from the operation or (b) you are due to undergo the operation in the next half hour.
Query: Which possibility do you prefer?


Parfit reckons that most people would prefer possibility (a). This suggests that we have a certain “Con Bias Toward the Future”. In other words, we prefer not to have negative experiences lying in our future.

Now, Parfit has his own reasons for discussing this case, and they will feature in part two, but for the time being what’s important is how two other philosophers — Brueckner and Fischer — have used this idea to respond to the Lucretian symmetry argument. Taking Parfit’s notion onboard, B&F argue that not only do we have a “Con” bias toward the future, we also have a “Pro” bias toward the future. In other words, given the option, we prefer to have positive experiences in the future. To see this, simply modify the Parfittian thought experiment:
 

Pleasure Drug: You are in the hospital to test some new drug. The drug gives you intense feelings of pleasure for approximately one hour. However, soon after you will forget everything. You wake up in your hospital bed and ask the nurse on-duty what your status is. She tells you that you either: (a) took the drug yesterday but have now forgotten; or (d) are due to take the drug later today.
Query: Which possibility do you prefer?


B&F suggest the answer is obvious: you would prefer (d). This, they argue, justifies their belief in the pro-bias toward the future. The gist of the idea is depicted below.
 

3. The Future Bias and the fear of Death

These biases are all well and good, and the thought experiments used to uncover them are interesting, but where does it get us? Surely, all they really show is that we are (or, at least, might be) biased toward the future. How can we use that fact to defeat the Lucretian argument?

It takes a bit of work, but we can eventually use it to undermine the analogy Lucretius tried to draw. That process starts with the following argument:

 

  • (6) We care about our future experiences in a way that we don’t care about our past experiences; more precisely: we prefer to have positive experiences in the future, and negative experiences (if necessary) in the past. 
  • (7) Death deprives us of future positive experiences; PNNB only deprives us of past positive experiences. 
  • (8) Therefore, death deprives us of something we care about, but PNNB does not.
 


This is clearly articulates the difference between the two cases. But it doesn’t quite get us to the rejection of premise (2). Premise (2) talks about death and PNNB being similar “in all important respects”. Before we can conclude that premise (2) is flawed we have to know that the deprivation of something we care about is an important difference between the two cases.

It is at this point that something called the Deprivation Thesis enters the fray. According to the deprivation thesis, something is bad for us if it deprives us of something we would have had but for that thing. It is a counterfactual principle, one that compares our welfare across possible worlds in order to determine whether the actual world is bad for us. If we append the deprivation thesis to the end of the previous argument...

 

  • (9) If X deprives us of something we care about, then X is bad for us.
 


…we can reject premise (2). This is depicted in the diagram below.
 



But is this really a persuasive rebuttal to the Lucretian argument? Is there not something slightly suspicious about appealing to the Deprivation thesis in order to defeat Lucretian symmetry, especially given that it was really this deprivation-based account of the badness of death that Lucretius was trying to undermine? We’ll look at these questions in part two.


John Danaher holds a PhD from University College Cork (Ireland) and is currently a lecturer in law at NUI Galway (Ireland). His research interests are eclectic, ranging broadly from philosophy of religion to legal theory, with particular interests in human enhancement and neuroethics. John blogs at http://philosophicaldisquisitions.blogspot.com/. You can follow him on twitter @JohnDanaher.
Print Email permalink (7) Comments (2455) Hits •  subscribe Share on facebook Stumble This submit to reddit submit to digg


COMMENTS


This is a really interesting argument, John.

What I wonder though is whether Lucretius is really making a point about the relationship between death and suffering. What he seems to be saying is that death is ultimately a “good” in that entails the absence of suffering and want- the same lack of suffering and want experienced before birth.

The future bias might cancel out here because the only choice available outside of non-being is suffering. Therefore we can look on death as a sort of “good.”





“1) The state of pre-natal non-being is not bad for us.

(2) Post-mortem non-being (death) is the same as pre-natal non-being, in all important respects.

(3) Therefore, death is not bad for us.”

Unfortunately this logic falls at the first fence since these non-existence states are neither “good” nor “bad” for us, then they are equally “not good” for us either? Back to square one?

Argument for “Ignorance” of any pre-natal/post-death experience can be used to “ease suffering” caused by fear and anxiety of death, and moreover, there are many other more therapeutic and beneficial arguments and rationale to overcome these fears, especially including the theosophical. Yet these arguments do not solve the dilemma “is death bad for us”?

However, “Premature death” IS bad. So the dilemma is now to decide what we reject as unacceptably premature?





1. Extensive suffering is often used as argument for euthanasia. Yet this by no measure makes death acceptable nor “good”.

2. Physical and psychological suffering, including anxiety and fear of death, CAN be mitigated and even overcome with deliberation, tenacity and enterprise.

3. Assuming suffering is mitigated, death will never be acceptable even after n+years, using the same rationale that premature death is not acceptable for us now, here today?

4. There can be no logical argument to justify death/demise as good where existence may prevail?

5. The Universe and biological evolution perpetuates life forces and copying of species DNA with great accuracy as existence is deemed logical as compared with non-existence?





To add further emphasis to point 5 above

6. By the same measure that impartial Universal forces perpetuate existence over non-existence, despite of any preferential thinking bias, Human, (and intelligent machine), minds may yet apply the same determination and logical argument for continued existence over demise and non-existence?





@CyngusX1:


I am not quite making the argument that suffering can be a justification for death, but this is one way to read Lucretius, and indeed is the stance taken by two of the world’s major religions-
Hinduism and Buddhism- where the problem isn’t death as is the assumption in Western culture, but constant rebirth. Fear of this suffering, or even the constant low level suffering or I should add dread at the weight of the mundane, seems an at least intuitively valid argument and seems to add a new element into the future orientation element in John’s piece.

I would add to suffering as in pain the weight of sheer boring mundane behaviors that lie in weight for those who would live forever.
Or, how many times would an immortal brush her teeth?





@ Rik

Sorry, my comment was in response to the questions posed from the article. However, your comment still does not justify death as “not bad for us”?

I think you have it wrong with your summation of eastern philosophies also. Indeed the goal is to escape samsara, yet neither of these advocate “ultimate death” and demise, nor suicide as means to mitigate suffering.

Buddhism advocates understanding and mitigation of suffering through dispassion and rejection of clinging and grasping, (wants, needs and emotion), however nirvana/nibbana does not equate to nihilism, and is not pursued by quickening of death.

Hinduism philosophies advaita, Vishishtadvaita, and dvaita which comprise most forms followed today do not advocate total demise nor euthanasia either, with advaita closest to Buddhist contemplation of emptiness, and the latter pertaining to eternal bliss and union with godhead.

All of the above rely on the attainment of enlightenment, for which “premature death” is obstruction.





@CyngusX1:

Oh, I have no desire to get into the minutiae of Buddhist or Hindu religious philosophy, but I think you have missed out on some important details.

Original Buddhist thought towards the question of suicide has some resemblance to the thoughts on suicide that were held by the stoics, that because life and the individual are not the ultimate value, suicide might sometimes be the courageous and proper thing to do.

In the early extant Buddhists scriptures, the Pāli Canon, the Buddha lauds the suicide of one person, Chana, as enlightenedand seems sympathetic to the suicides of two others- Godhika, and Vakkail. 

In terms of Hinduism, there we find the idea of prayopavesa, which is essentially suicide through fasting. This practice is reserved for only the highest religious persons who have shed all social obligations.

Both these Buddhist and Hindu concepts make sense within the frame of reference their faiths provide. Namely, that the goal of the individual is not to continue to exist, but to escape the cycle of birth-suffering and death. 

Both acknowledge the danger of making suicide a generally acceptable principle including the reality that people who are in an emotionally heightened state might see such an option as an easy escape from their pain, and who because of those who love and depend upon them will suffer from such suicides they discourage it. Instead, suicide is reserved for only those who have reached the highest spiritual state, and are free of social dependents. 

I think the meaning of Lucretius’ thoughts on death cannot be properly understood without keeping this something similar to the Buddhist or Hindu view as regards to the close relationship between life and suffering in mind. If you read Lucretius’ Of the Nature of Things you will see that he thinks the reason we fear death is that we imagine (while alive of course!) what suffering we will undergo when dead when, even to go so far as all the good things we will miss out on when not here, but if we looked at it squarely we would see death entails no suffering at all- indeed the end of all suffering. 





YOUR COMMENT (IEET's comment policy)

Login or Register to post a comment.

Next entry: Covering the Future Beat: Managing Futureshock when Writing for a Mass Audience

Previous entry: The demand for biofuels from the African continent

HOME | ABOUT | FELLOWS | STAFF | EVENTS | SUPPORT  | CONTACT US
SECURING THE FUTURE | LONGER HEALTHIER LIFE | RIGHTS OF THE PERSON | ENVISIONING THE FUTURE
CYBORG BUDDHA PROJECT | AFRICAN FUTURES PROJECT | JOURNAL OF EVOLUTION AND TECHNOLOGY

RSSIEET Blog | email list | newsletter |
The IEET is a 501(c)3 non-profit, tax-exempt organization registered in the State of Connecticut in the United States.

Contact: Executive Director, Dr. James J. Hughes,
Williams 119, Trinity College, 300 Summit St., Hartford CT 06106 USA 
Email: director @ ieet.org     phone: 860-297-2376