A Legal Perspective on Humanity, Personhood, and Species Boundaries
Linda MacDonald Glenn
2003-06-10 00:00:00
URL

An analysis of the law adds a further layer of complexity to the "moral confusion," especially because the law, at least in the United States, does not require humanness to be a necessary condition for "personhood." A historical review of the law reveals that nonhuman animals (as well as slaves, women, and children) have been considered "property," while nonhuman entities, such as corporations, municipalities, and ships, have been recognized and given rights as "persons" (Glenn 2003). Yet, slowly and over time (hundreds of years), legal and moral notions of "persons" and "human rights" have evolved and expanded. Despite intermittent setbacks, the overall history of the U.S. Constitution has been one of increasing protection and expansion of individual rights and liberties. Although there has been no attempt on the part of any legislature or court to attempt to define "human," there have been proposed definitions in academic literature, legal and philosophical (Glenn 2003).

Robert and Baylis set forth two standard Western frameworks for attributing moral status, both of a hierarchical nature, then declare them to be incommensurable. Rather than declaring these frameworks to be incommensurable, I would argue that this presents an opportunity to examine other frameworks for attributing moral status, including a wholistic or interdependent approach. As Robert and Baylis note, the idea of the Great Chain of Being has crumbled; alternative frameworks can provide commensurability, starting with the premise that both human and nonhuman life has intrinsic value and is worthy of moral status. This is a view consistent with environmental and global ethics. Does this premise somehow "denigrate" humanity's status? Not if it is applied with the perspective of stewardship (Glenn 2003).

Which leads to another important question raised by the spawning of highly intelligent nonhuman beings through technology: What moral and legal obligations do we have to these novel entities that we have helped to create? Phrased another way, what ethical obligations might science have to promote the survivability of the novel sentient chimera, a de novo endangered species? Is it comparable to the obligation that parents have to their children, because their actions brought them into existence?

Some in the bioethics community have argued that a complete ban on experimentation with human embryos is warranted—that research that blends human nature with other natures alters our understanding of personhood, undermining our notion of human dignity and human rights (Annas, Andrews, and Isasi 2002). But such a ban assumes that tampering solely with the human species presents a meaningful risk; the ban does not anticipate that human genes inserted into another species might create a sentient life-form that is worthy of moral respect and status. Should every human gene sequence be banned from insertion into another species? As Robert and Baylis point out with their introductory examples, we are far beyond that point. Current U.S. and Canadian laws do not prohibit the patenting and marketing of DNA sequences, cell lines, or stem cells of human origin. How many human gene sequences would it take to make another species have those human characteristics we hold so dear? When does a "nonhuman" with human genes become human, deserving full human rights? As Robert and Baylis deftly illustrate, the answer is not as clear-cut as some would like it to be. When scientists applied for a patent for a half-human, half-chimpanzee, the U.S. Patent and Trademark Office denied the application, claiming such a patent would violate the constitutional protection against slavery, as set forth in Thirteenth Amendment.

Robert and Baylis rightly point out that these developments might force us to revisit some of our current patterns of behavior toward human and nonhuman animals. If traditional notions of personhood prevail, society runs the risk of denying essential basic liberties to sentient beings. Rather than attempting to freeze our human nature, such as it currently is, in order to preserve human dignity and rights, perhaps we need to rephrase the question: "How [End Page 27] can we preserve human rights and human dignity despite the fact that our 'humanness' might no longer be the exclusive possession of Homo sapiens?" And as different forms of intelligent life are created through transgenics and genetic engineering, the courts, legislatures, and legal community will be forced to determine where these creations fall on the person-property continuum.

References

Annas, G. J., L. B. Andrews, and R. M. Isasi. 2002. Protecting the endangered human: Toward an international treaty prohibiting cloning and inheritable alterations. American Journal of Law & Medicine 28:151-78.

Glenn, L. M. 2003. Biotechnology at the margins of personhood: An evolving legal paradigm. Journal of Evolution and Technology, 13:1-112.

Robert, J. S., and F. Baylis. 2003. Crossing species boundaries. The American Journal of Bioethics 3(3):1-13.