Institute for Ethics and Emerging Technologies


The IEET is a 501(c)3 non-profit, tax-exempt organization registered in the State of Connecticut in the United States. Please give as you are able, and help support our work for a brighter future.


Search the IEET
Subscribe and Contribute to:


Technoprogressive? BioConservative? Huh?
Quick overview of biopolitical points of view




whats new at ieet

The First Nuclear Power Plant in Belarus Is a Dangerous Fiasco

The Science of Fear-Mongering: How to Protect Your Mind from Demagogues

Rising Sea Levels Threaten Nearly a Trillion Dollars Worth of US Homes

Rachel O’Dwyer on Bitcoin, Blockchains and the Digital Commons

Augmented Reality: Pokémon GO Is Only the Beginning

No Mans Sky: A Deist Simulated Universe


ieet books

Philosophical Ethics: Theory and Practice
Author
John G Messerly


comments

RJP8915 on 'No Mans Sky: A Deist Simulated Universe' (Aug 26, 2016)

instamatic on 'No Mans Sky: A Deist Simulated Universe' (Aug 26, 2016)

RJP8915 on 'No Mans Sky: A Deist Simulated Universe' (Aug 26, 2016)

instamatic on 'No Mans Sky: A Deist Simulated Universe' (Aug 26, 2016)

RJP8915 on 'No Mans Sky: A Deist Simulated Universe' (Aug 26, 2016)

instamatic on 'No Mans Sky: A Deist Simulated Universe' (Aug 24, 2016)

almostvoid on 'Augmented Reality: Pokémon GO Is Only the Beginning' (Aug 24, 2016)







Subscribe to IEET News Lists

Daily News Feed

Longevity Dividend List

Catastrophic Risks List

Biopolitics of Popular Culture List

Technoprogressive List

Trans-Spirit List



JET

Enframing the Flesh: Heidegger, Transhumanism, and the Body as “Standing Reserve”

Moral Enhancement and Political Realism

Intelligent Technologies and Lost Life

Hottest Articles of the Last Month


Op-ed: Climate Change Is the Most Urgent Existential Risk
Aug 7, 2016
(5145) Hits
(4) Comments

Consciousness, Reality, and the Simulation Hypothesis
Aug 4, 2016
(4582) Hits
(15) Comments

Shedding Light on Peter Thiel’s Dark Enlightenment
Aug 15, 2016
(4464) Hits
(2) Comments

Cognitive Buildings!
Aug 1, 2016
(3534) Hits
(1) Comments



IEET

Print Email permalink (6) Comments (2440) Hits •  subscribe Share on facebook Stumble This submit to reddit submit to digg


Should We Be Grateful for Death?


John Danaher
By John Danaher
Philosophical Disquisitions

Posted: Mar 1, 2016

Most people think death is bad. They approach it with a degree of trepidation, possibly even denial. The prospect is particularly acute for someone who does not believe in an afterlife. Could such a person ever view death as a gift, something for which they should be grateful? That’s the intriguing question asked by Mikel Burley in his article “Atheism and the Gift of Death”. I want to take a look at his answer in this post.

(Previous post on existential gratitude

I’ll start by dismissing a relatively trivial sense in which a non-believer can view death as a gift. They can view it as a gift when the life they are living is unremittingly bad. They could be suffering tremendous pain due to a terminal illness. There might be no prospect of recovery. Death could be, consequently, the only possible release from the burden of existence. A person in such a state could view death as a gift. In fact, they might even want to hasten death. This position is common in defences of euthanasia.

I dismiss this sense of a death-as-a-gift not because it is uninteresting or unimportant. It is clearly both. But it is also relatively trivial. The deeper question is whether someone whose life is otherwise good can welcome its end as a gift. In other words, can death be viewed as a gift no matter what the life it ends involves?

1. The Standard Religious View

Let’s start by looking at the religious view. The typical monotheistic position maintains that there is an afterlife (heaven/paradise) in which we (and all our friends and family members) will live after we die. In this place, we will be united with our creator (God) and will be rewarded with an existence that is greater than what we previously had on earth.

This typical religious position makes it relatively easy to conceptualise death as a gift. It is an opportunity to shake off this veil of tears. Burley uses a nice quote from Hermann Lange to underscore the point. Lange was a Catholic priest in Nazi Germany. He publicly opposed the Nazi party and was executed for his troubles. Just before his execution he sent a letter to his parents:

For, after all, death means homecoming. The gift we thereupon receive is so unimaginably great that all human joys pale beside it, and the bitterness of death as such — however sinister it may appear to our human nature — is completely conquered by it.

The logic applies both to those whose lives are going well and those whose lives are going badly. If their life is going badly then you they be compensated for this by the unimaginably great joys in the afterlife. And if their life is going well, then they should still regard death as a gift because the joys they will experience in heaven are so much greater than those they currently experience.

In essence, according to this religious view, death is a gift because it allows for our lives to continue in a superior form. There is no way that an atheist (who disbelieves in an afterlife) could embrace a similar view.

2. An Alternative Religious View

But this typical religious view has been challenged by some religious scholars. They consider its conception of the afterlife as a temporal continuation of this life (only in a much better form) to be ethically and metaphysically flawed. Nicholas Lash is one such scholar. He doesn’t conceive of the afterlife in temporal terms. He does not think that we continue to live on in some cloudy paradise, dancing and frolicking with our friends and families. Instead, he thinks we will join with God and partake of His eternal (non-temporal) existence.

On this view, the afterlife is less a continuation of life here on earth and more a completion of life. It is the end of our existence as we know it and the transition to something else. Lash thinks that the continuation view is ethically damaging. We have duties to perform here on earth. We should take these duties seriously. If we think that the present life is simply a waiting room to something better; and that no matter how bad things presently are they will be recompensed in the afterlife; then we run the risk of thinking that our present duties do not ultimately matter. This can erode ethical sensibilities. And the risk is not entirely negligible. There is a destructive and apocalyptic tendency in some religions which is in part driven by the belief that the afterlife will compensate for everything.

This alternative religious view is interesting. It still conceives of death as a gift, but it does so in a different way. It conceives of death as a gift because it is the moment at which life is completed, not continued in a better form. It seems more plausible for there to be an atheistic equivalent of this view. There is nothing obviously metaphysically out of line with an atheistic conception of death as a fitting capstone or end to life taken as a whole. As Burley puts it:

Despite the atheist’s being unable to join the Christian in regarding death as a completion of that which stands in eternal relation to God, he may nevertheless concur that death constitutes the final moment of a finite whole, and thereby gives a determinate structure or shape to that life. To see death as a gift may be to regard it as that which completes and to some extent defines who one is…When one’s death actually occurs, life becomes complete; in so far as one’s life as a whole is a gift, so is one’s death, for it is one of the conditions of having a recognizably human life at all.

(Burley 2012, 538).

This is a somewhat complex view. It presumes that the atheist is grateful for their life. Whether such an emotional reaction is appropriate for the atheist is a contentious matter, but one that I explored in a recent blogpost. For the time being we will assume that the atheist can indeed be grateful for living. This is usually premised on the belief that life itself is good (i.e. has positive value) and so we should be grateful for the opportunity to live it. What Burley is proposing is that we add to this the view that death is necessary to give the atheist’s life-as-a-whole its value. How can we make sense of this?

3. How does death complete the atheist’s life?

We can start by considering an obvious objection. There is a life extension movement out there. Members of this movement think that medical breakthroughs can be leveraged to enable us to extend our lives indefinitely. In my experience, most members of this movement tend to be non-religious. They do not believe in an afterlife. They accept the claim that life is good and hence something we can be grateful for. They dispute the claim that death gives life value. They favour the polar opposite. They think that death robs life of its value. We should do everything we can to avoid it.

If Burley’s suggestion is to gain any traction, it must be able to show why this view is flawed. Burley doesn’t attempt a full-blown critique. He isn’t trying to show that the atheist should view death as a gift always and everywhere. He argues for a more abstract view: particular instances of dying could be bad, but mortality itself (i.e. the fact that life must come to end) could be essential for value. Burley chooses a popular line of support for this: the arguments of Bernard Williams in his famous article ‘The Makropulos Case: Reflections on the Tedium of Morality’. I’ve covered these arguments before in pretty exhaustive detail. In essence, they maintain that an immortal life (one in which death is not possible) would be bad in various ways. The two main ways are that it would erode individual identity (you cannot live forever and maintain a single consistent identity) and that it would lead to boredom. Other philosophers, like Martha Nussbaum and Aaron Smuts, offer similar arguments. Nussbaum claims that an immortal life would rob our decisions of their normative significance; and Smuts argues that an immortal life would take away the good of achievement. These arguments can be challenged, of course, but if they work they lend support to the kind of view that Burley is trying to push. They suggest that mortality is essential to a life with the sorts of values we deem important to life as it is currently lived. (Samuel Scheffler has also supported this kind of argument and I covered his contribution in a previous blogpost).

Burley covers two objections to this line of thought. The first holds that the atheist still cannot view death as a gift because in order for one to conceive of death as a gift there must be a recipient of the gift. But, of course, if you cease to exist after your death you cannot receive the gift. One can quibble with the details of this. You will still be alive during the process of dying, so perhaps the gift accrues at that point. This seems somewhat unpalatable. Alternatively, you could embrace the idea of posthumous gifts. Burley notes that honours are sometimes conferred on deceased persons. Even if those people continue to exist in another form, they are definitely not around to receive those honours. This suggests that recipients may not be necessary for gifts. Gifts may be possible sub specie aeternitatis.

The second, and slightly more interesting, objection focuses on the strength of Burley’s argument. Burley claims that, if he is right, it is possible for the atheist to view death as a gift. But so what? Mere possibility is not enough in this debate. It may be possible for the atheist to do this but should they? Will they?

Burley has some interesting things to say about this. First he suggests that philosophical argument has a limited role to play in changing how people will view their lives and deaths:

To come to see one’s life as a gift, and perhaps one’s death as well, and to express gratitude for these things, is not a matter of assenting to the truth or plausibility of certain propositions….It is more like coming to see life, or the world, under a different aspect — coming to feel the compulsion of that way of looking at things. And that compulsion is unlikely to be generated by means of arguments, at least in any formal sense of ‘argument’.

(Burley 2012, 542)

So what will generate the compulsion?

More likely, I think, is that someone will come across the words of individuals who, either in life or in literature, express the attitude concerned, and will come, gradually or perhaps in some cases suddenly, to feel an affinity with those forms of words; will recognise that speaking of life and death, and many other things besides, as gifts expresses something with which she can identify.

(Burley 2012, 542)

This may be the function of certain literary passages from famous atheists. I think, in particular, of Richard Dawkins’s famous ‘We are going to die’ passage, which I analysed on a previous occasion.

  

To sum up, Burley is arguing that it is possible for an atheist to view death as a gift, not just because it sometimes offers a release from a horrendous existence, but because it gives shape and purpose to a life that is valuable. I find all of this very interesting.


John Danaher holds a PhD from University College Cork (Ireland) and is currently a lecturer in law at NUI Galway (Ireland). His research interests are eclectic, ranging broadly from philosophy of religion to legal theory, with particular interests in human enhancement and neuroethics. John blogs at http://philosophicaldisquisitions.blogspot.com/. You can follow him on twitter @JohnDanaher.
Print Email permalink (6) Comments (2441) Hits •  subscribe Share on facebook Stumble This submit to reddit submit to digg


COMMENTS


If death was such a gift, professor Danaher, most people would be lining up to be voluntary targets for firing squads. It must be built into our genetics to try to survive. Religions are basically pyschological mechanisms in an attempt to accomplish this survival. When we attend many funerals, the tears we see are not tears of joy, but tears of loss, frustration, and despair.

How is the Atheist view of death? Well, to quote Sommerset Maugham (not my favorite English guy) “When people cease believing in God, the do not believe in nothing, they believe in anything.” This may or may not be true, but it does eplain the burgeoning of ideologies, during the 20th century. Stalin, Mao, and even old, Adolf, were not God guys, but ideologists with god-complexes, and apparently, so were their obedient followers. I suspect that our own personal neurobiology deternines whether we are believers or not, and thus, not something, attributable to intelligence, or moral character, as many choose to believe. In my opinion, the best of the Atheists are people like Dawkins who look at which religion is the most threatening to free thinking and target them. For this, I applaud Dawkins as well as for his interesting ideas. He does not discriminate, but he is discriminating in his judgements.

My suspicion, is that both the Atheist and the Religious believer (gullable is ok by me) is that their is a need for survival, with a God, without a God, with an order of baked Cod, however we conjur it all up. It is something that is desired by most, even if unattainable, as a beneficial good. The is work undone, tragedies, to be remediated, new tales to be told, and eventually, according to a recent physics paper, the Galaxy, may be at hand (Yeah, like in X thousands of years!). So there are reasons to live, even if we cannot. Post mortem restoration is probably more than you wish to discuss, at this point, so, I will leave it here. Stimulating article this.

Mitch





The idea that death as a completion is beneficial is consistent, but that is no reason to believe it.  Why feel the need for such a completion?





I agree with Spud. Rationalizing death and forcing oneself to see it as something good can be a sensible way to cope with the idea of death (I guess) if that’s the best one can do, but it’s much inferior to the real thing, which is avoiding death.

Current advances show that sooner or later we will be able to avoid death, and that is _much better_ than learning to love it.

Unfortunately, that won’t happen in time for our generation, and probably not for our children either. Perhaps our grand-children who are alive by the end of the century will be able to stay young and healthy indefinitely, in biological or robotic bodies.

For us, I am afraid the “post mortem restoration” in the far future mentioned by Spud is the only hope. It’s hope in the far fringes of science as we understand it today, but again, believe me, is _much better_ than learning to love death.





The article only skims the surface of this topic as there are many more religious or semi-religious views of death which are at least equally important. Also, one can be an atheist who accepts the existence of reincarnation or the afterlife in a non religious sense and think of death if not as a gift then at least as a “helpful release” or a “good change”.





“they maintain that an immortal life (one in which death is not possible) would be bad in various ways. The two main ways are that it would erode individual identity (you cannot live forever and maintain a single consistent identity) and that it would lead to boredom.”

I make reference to Max More’s thesis: “The Diachronic Self: Identity, Continuity, Transformation” and David Deutsch’s book “The Beginning of Infinity: Explanations that Transform the World” with reference to the ideas of infinity and universality.

Regarding the first point (it would erode individual identity) It is not reasonable to suppose that the earlier you will “contain” what you will become. The three year old is not “lost” in any meaningful sense because he or she grows into an adult and “puts away childish things”. Similarly, an “adult” of conventional maturity—say seventy years—would not be lost in any meaningful sense if he or she should grow into a further adulthood of a billion years and put away the relatively childish things of the seventy year old.

Regarding the second point (it would lead to boredom) It should be clear that if we aspire to unlimited growth we will need to find effective means of “garbage disposal”: true acceptance of the death of no-longer viable ideas through effective criticism—Popperian selection. Max Planck remarked that physics advanced one funeral at a time.  Those deaths were necessary for the advance of physics because the scientists had no effective “delete” mechanism to cleanse their neural connectomes so they could take a fresh look at the world. Of the seven categories of renewal in Aubrey de Grey’s SENS program for indefinite life extension three categories involve garbage removal—garbage within cells (lipofuscans), garbage between cells (amyloids) and cells that are themselves garbage (senescent cells)). This fourth category of garbage removal will also be necessary, and it will require gaining an understanding of the mind for it to be implemented. There is no reason our personal identity should be tied to obsolete ideas. Making the distinction will be a necessary part of the solution. When we have it, the crux of the problem of boredom will be resolved.





I have no problem with identity evolving over time.  It happens whatever the lifespan, and its one of the things that gives life meaning. Its also the very thing which negates boredom as the other objection to indefinite life-extension.





YOUR COMMENT (IEET's comment policy)

Login or Register to post a comment.

Next entry: Artificial Intelligence – Achieving Consciousness

Previous entry: Assessing Intelligence with Standardized Testing Has a Limited Purpose

HOME | ABOUT | FELLOWS | STAFF | EVENTS | SUPPORT  | CONTACT US
SECURING THE FUTURE | LONGER HEALTHIER LIFE | RIGHTS OF THE PERSON | ENVISIONING THE FUTURE
CYBORG BUDDHA PROJECT | AFRICAN FUTURES PROJECT | JOURNAL OF EVOLUTION AND TECHNOLOGY

RSSIEET Blog | email list | newsletter |
The IEET is a 501(c)3 non-profit, tax-exempt organization registered in the State of Connecticut in the United States.

East Coast Contact: Executive Director, Dr. James J. Hughes,
56 Daleville School Rd., Willington CT 06279 USA 
Email: director @ ieet.org     phone: 860-428-1837

West Coast Contact: Managing Director, Hank Pellissier
425 Moraga Avenue, Piedmont, CA 94611
Email: hank @ ieet.org